Fill This Form To Receive Instant Help

Help in Homework
trustpilot ratings
google ratings


Homework answers / question archive / Title: The Moral Life: An Introductory Reader in Ethics and Literature Author: Louis P

Title: The Moral Life: An Introductory Reader in Ethics and Literature Author: Louis P

Writing

Title: The Moral Life: An Introductory Reader in Ethics and Literature Author: Louis P. Pojman and Lewis Vaughn, editors Publisher: Oxford University Press Edition information: Sixth Edition ISBN: 9780190607845

 

"Global Economic Justice - Analysis Paper"

Read the Text: Title: The Moral Life: An Introductory Reader in Ethics and Literature Author: Louis P. Pojman and Lewis Vaughn, editors Publisher: Oxford University Press Edition information: Sixth Edition ISBN: 9780190607845

 

Read Chapter 16 of The Moral Life, “Global Economic Justice.” We are reading the whole chapter.

Along with a brief introduction, there are four distinct passages in this chapter.  Read all of them carefully.

Ask yourself if you can agree with each author’s arguments and think about why or why not.

 

Write and Post your Analysis Paper

title the submission, “Global Economic Justice – Analysis Paper.”  You may, of course, have a different or more creative title on the paper itself!

This analysis paper will primarily be about the readings from the unit on Global Economic Justice but you may want to consider other passages from throughout our text, The Moral Life. You have quite a bit of freedom in how you respond – however, be sure to give direct answers and provide evidence and analysis in your own words.

Here is the writing prompt:

Beginning on page 883 of the textbook, Title: The Moral Life: An Introductory Reader in Ethics and Literature Author: Louis P. Pojman and Lewis Vaughn, editors Publisher: Oxford University Press Edition information: Sixth Edition ISBN: 9780190607845

  we are presented with three groups of responses to world hunger.  Each group has slightly differing views inside of it.

1. Strong egalitarianism.  Egalitarians generally believe that because all people have the same moral worth, all people are entitled to the world's resources.  On varying levels, human beings who have wealth are required to share it.  In the case of Peter Singer, we must forgo luxuries and perhaps anything beyond basic needs to provide for the hungry.

2. Negative rights and lifeboat ethics.  There is no obligation from wealthy nations to help those in need.  Garrett Hardin moves a step further with this idea and argues that by giving to the needy, the wealthy nations of the world may in fact be perpetuating hunger or making the problem worse.  

3. Reasonable Beneficence.  The duty of helping others must be weighed alongside other duties.  Helping others must be weighed in accordance with helping one's self, or in the case of a wealthy nation - the entire nation.  Timmerman's passage generally follows this position.

Using all that you have learned in this course, choose ONE of these ethical responses and thoroughly analyze it for its effectiveness. You may choose a response with which you agree OR one with which you disagree. In either case, explain what is beneficial AND what is harmful in the response – including to whom it is harmful or beneficial. Part of the grade for this paper will be determined by the use of your examples and counter-examples, as well as your analysis of those examples and counter-examples.

DO NOT analyze all three responses - only analyze ONE position and then argue for or against it.

This is an analysis paper, so you will be writing a longer paper, 3-4 pages double spaced, 11/12 point font (900-1,100 words) and you will need to provide analysis.  Analysis, in this case, means that you will need to provide examples from the text (and cite them appropriately), and then provide your own insights to evaluate those examples for their effectiveness.  I have tried to design the question that about 1,000 words will be needed for an appropriate answer, but do not be afraid to write up to 1,200 words.

This is an academic paper, so include these three main parts:

1. Provide an introductory paragraph where you clearly state which ethical response you will be analyzing and if you will argue it to be a mostly effective response to world hunger, or a mostly ineffective response.  This is your thesis for the paper.  This should be in your own words with no citations.

2. In a main body of 3-5 short paragraphs, provide examples from the passages, and provide your own analysis.   You should provide examples that support your claim, and counter examples that do not support your claims and your responses to them.  Your analysis of the examples you provide should answer some (not necessarily all) of these kinds of questions:  What duties do more wealthy nations have to poorer nations?  Should a nation, community or individual person be obligated to help others who are in need?  Is feeding the hungry something that is supererogatory (that is, beyond the call of “duty”) or something that should be regulated, obligated or somehow legislated?  Please know that you have flexibility, but be sure to be clear in your presentation and argumentation.  Each of your paragraphs in the main body of your paper must have a cited example from the text.

3.  Provide a conclusion that restates your thesis that you introduced in the Introduction and shows that your arguments have provided enough evidence to back up your claim.  Your conclusion should emphasize the importance of the examples and analysis you have provided. This should be in your own words with no citations.

The length and requirements are similar to the previous analysis papers, so read them carefully:

When you cite the text, include the author.  For example:  Sartre says, “Ethics is cool,” (pg. 595, TML). – note: not an actual quote!  Try not to include very long or repetitive quotations.  Focus on your own original thinking!

Do not consult outside sources for your analysis paper.  Papers that use outside sources or are plagiarized will receive a 0/100 score.   

PLEASE NOTE THAT NO OUTSIDE SOURCES ARE TO BE USED ON ANY WRITING ASSIGNMENT IN THIS COURSE. 

No plagiarized work pls.

 

 

 

 

 

THIS WILL HELP IN WRITING THE PAPER…. LECTURES PROVIDED BY THE PROFESSOR

 

 

Global Economic Justice

In this chapter there are four passages, ending with Timmerman's reply to Peter Singer's passage, Famine, Affluence and Morality. Throughout the book, we have read and studied ethical theories, moral issues and their applications.  The major ethical dilemma with which this last chapter grapples is poverty and hunger on a global scale.  Garrett Hardin argued in the previous chapter that there are no “technological solutions” to certain problems in the world.  Whether or not you agree with Hardin’s arguments, there is no denying that hunger is a global issue.

The introduction to this chapter begins with the rather stark and shocking contrast between the “haves and have-nots.”  Statistics can sometimes convey desired messages, but the message may be lost in the numbers.  However, most scholars seem to agree that about one-third of the earth’s population is under-nourished and simply does not have enough to eat.  They estimated, at the time the book was written, that about one billion of the earth’s six billion inhabitants are hungry or malnourished.  The world population is now estimated at 7.3 billion, and continues to grow!  Those numbers seem a bit overwhelming to me, and perhaps these statistics will cloud our judgment a little bit.  Perhaps it should and perhaps it should not – that is something else with which we may grapple.

We will notice that the authors in this chapter rely on ethical theories we have studied throughout the course to provide evidence for their arguments.  There are references to utilitarianism and deontology.  Ideas in virtue ethics are clearly present, and if we pay careful attention, we should see elements of the ethics of care.  Issues surrounding the autonomy and dignity of people will be evident as well as other concepts and ideas we have discussed throughout the course.  I think that this is a fitting (and perhaps enormously difficult) moral dilemma with which to end our course!

The question for this chapter is then posed on page 883: “what are we – the secure and comfortable denizens of the West – obligated to do for the impoverished, starving and dying of the Third World?

Perhaps some individuals in the “West” are not as “secure and comfortable” as we would perhaps like to be.  However, the point that the authors are trying to make is a very general one.  In comparison to the rest of the world, there are certain nations that are more “affluent” (rich in resources) than others across the globe.  The United States, for example, is more affluent as a nation than any nation in Africa or South America.  There is no real dispute to this.  So the question remains, what are the duties that the United States, and other more affluent nations, should have to less affluent nations?

On pages 883-5, there are three groups of answers provided.  There is, of course, a wide spectrum of belief or opinion on the matter, but you should understand these three points on the spectrum.  The first group is the “strong egalitarians” who say that we are “obligated to share the earth’s resources with all those in need.”  Equality is the highest priority, so we must equally distribute wealth.  The second group says that there is no obligation or duty to feed the hungry.  In fact, we actually have a stronger duty to not feed them because this might negatively change our own position.  Note well the difference between having “a duty to help” (this is related to someone else’s positive rights) and having “a duty to not interfere” (this is related to someone else’s negative rights).  For this second group, we have no obligation to help, but we do have a duty to not interfere with someone else’s “negative” rights which could make someone’s situation worse.  (I am reminded of the “Prime Directive” in Star Trek for any “Trekkies” out there – if that makes no sense, please disregard!)  The third group takes a more moderate approach and recognizes the duty of beneficence and generosity, and weighs this duty against other obligations and rights.

In the passages, you will notice some important terms and ideas.  The moral obligation to do good to others and avoid harming them is known as a duty of beneficence.  Egalitarianism is discussed in this chapter and egalitarians argue that since all persons have equal worth, they are all entitled to equal portions of the world's essential goods.  It is important to notice that the utilitarian view on aiding the poor and hungry, used by BOTH Singer and Hardin, has the potential to lead to very different results and responses to world hunger.

Garrett Hardin (and later Singer, too) often cite statistics involving world population growth rates, poverty rates and financial information to show the massive effect amounts of money and food required to feed and take care of the entire world.  One of the hard parts about using readings like these in a college course is that the information is out of date the moment it is printed.  The editors of this book have taken a certain kind of approach and they have supplied the more “classic” and some time-tested essays by important leaders in particular areas rather than opting for the latest groundbreaking studies that may or may not stand the “test of time.”  Therefore, the statistics may seem “dated” yet they are generally fairly accurate because they are based on older studies and have been more tested.  The interpretations, however, are of course up for debate and we can see the drastically different conclusions at which the authors of these passages arrive.

However, be careful in reading about their interpretations and think for yourself!  The numbers presented only present a snapshot of certain situations that the writer intends to interpret and then recommend actions.  I mention it here because some of these statistics have changed over time (e.g. populations change and growth rates change in many nations) but the theories behind the interpretations of this data may also evolve in different ways.  For those of you who have some “extra” time or are particularly interested, the US Government has a “World Population Clock” at https://www.census.gov/popclock/ (Links to an external site.)   I provide a fair warning, if you are interested in numbers, you can spend quite a bit of time looking at this interesting data – so try not to let it detract from your work!

I will briefly provide some comments and highlight the important issues in the passages.  As always, you will need to read the text for the most complete presentation of ideas and your fullest understanding of the issues at hand.

 

Living on a Lifeboat – Garrett Hardin

As we should remember from the previous unit, mutual ruin from a well-meaning system of sharing is what Garrett Hardin calls the tragedy of the commons.  “The Tragedy of the Commons” is another passage by Hardin, and it appears in the chapter on “Our Duties to the Environment.”  Some of the same metaphors and ideas from the previous passage are discussed again here. 

Hardin’s focus here is on presenting his idea that providing food to needy countries will eventually result in a larger catastrophe where there is suffering and death on a massive scale.  Therefore, affluent nations like the United States should withhold aid (primarily food and medicine) from poorer countries.  The reason for withholding is not simply greed or self-centeredness, he argues, but to avoid future catastrophes on a massive global scale.  Nations that are incredibly poor increase in population much more rapidly than affluent nations do.  He argues that this can only end in a catastrophe, and by withholding food supply this will force poorer nations to adjust and be able to provide their own resources to their own population. 

His metaphor of the lifeboat is meant to be a better solution than that of “spaceship earth.”  The lifeboat metaphor is discussed on pages 888-9.  The picture is clear – the lifeboat has a capacity of 60, with 50 people already aboard.  150 other people are swimming for their lives.  Do we choose only 10 to rescue?  If we attempt to rescue everyone, everyone will die.  He even claims “complete justice, complete catastrophe” (p. 888) which seems to justify a certain level of acceptable “injustice” and perhaps also implies that it is not just that some people in the world have plenty while others have little or nothing.

Hardin discusses the metaphor of the lifeboat, concerns about reproduction and overpopulation, ideas to what he calls (a “ruinous system” of) “commons” including a world food bank, and issues related to immigration.  Hardin’s arguments are perhaps sometimes extreme and overstated, which the passage by Murdoch and Oaten aim to show.  As you read through Hardin’s arguments, read carefully.  His goal does not seem to be to offend or even discriminate against poorer nations, but rather work toward solutions for preserving the world for posterity or future generations.

One important example about which I will mention a little more is Hardin’s views with regard to immigration. During the section “Immigration creates a commons” Hardin asks “How curious it is that we so seldom discuss immigration these days?” (p. 897).   There have been some significant changes in the United States since 1974, when this article was published, and immigration is now more often discussed – but perhaps not in the same way that Hardin relates here.  Hardin shows that in the previous two generations (perhaps three, now) that all of the “pejorative terms” he mentions were in the popular press and it was most certainly not considered wrong or “politically incorrect” to use these racial references that are now considered very offensive.  He argues that immigrants, and in particular Mexican-Americans, are exploited as “cheap labor” and this leads him to argue for immigration control.  As you should notice, he does not seem to argue for “closing the door” on any kind of immigration into the United States, but rather monitoring the current population by monitoring birth rates and death rates and allowing immigration to ensure close to “zero population growth” as a kind of optimal goal.  It seems that for Hardin ending immigration is not a goal.  Rather, the goal is attempting to regulate population growth (to near-zero) and he believes this may ensure the survival of a certain way of life in this country and avoid overpopulation.

There are subtleties to Hardin’s arguments and while the critics (in the very next passage) accuse Hardin of being “simplistic” in his analysis and particularly his use of metaphors, I am not sure if we can say that everything he argues is “simple,” even if we disagree with some or all of his views.  I hope that this makes sense and I will repeat for some emphasis: Hardin’s critics say his analysis is “simplistic” but that does not mean that his ideas are “simple.”

 

A Critique of Lifeboat Ethics – William W. Murdoch and Alan Oaten

Murdoch and Oaten criticize Hardin’s metaphor of the “lifeboat” and argue against the validity of his claims.  As I noted in the last section above, they charge that Hardin’s analysis is too “simplistic.”

One of the main criticisms of the lifeboat metaphor in this passage is that the lifeboats – the nations of the world – have had quite a bit of interactions over hundreds of years.  In fact, it seems that many of the poorer nations have been exploited by the richer nations.  This exploitation may have been initiated in the colonial period, but it arguably continues to the present day.  One powerful example, discussed here and in other passages, is that many poor nations rely on “cash crops” rather than “food crops” to support themselves.  If a country grows cacao beans and coffee beans, as many African nations do – then they must rely on importing food to feed the people within their borders.  There then exists a strong reliance upon other nations and the divide between “rich” and “poor” is maintained and arguably grows wider.  Hardin said, and others seem to agree, that the “rich get richer and the poor get poorer” but they clearly differ on what to do about it.  Be sure you see these differences, as it will be important for understanding the different views presented in this chapter.

Murdoch and Oaten note on page 907 that “The fact is that enough food is now produced to feed the world’s population adequately” but that the problem is with the unequal distribution of the food.  From reading the Hardin passage, it seems that he may agree with the truth of this claim, but Hardin then argues that, in the face of knowing that, the United States should still not provide aid to poorer nations in the name of saving future generations.   

This passage from Murdoch and Oaten leads to a section “costs, gains and difficulties” that lists six measures on page 914 to aid poorer nations.  While it seems they recommend the U.S. take the lead in providing aid, Murdoch and Oaten do not think that the amount of aid required would cause a decline in the lifestyle of Americans.  They even go as far to say that Hardin’s view “bears no relation to reality” (p. 915) because according to their criticism he argues something like “it is either them or us.”  I leave it to you to decide if that is what he is really saying or if his critics are being a little unfair.  As you will notice if you read this passage (and the others) carefully, there is a significant amount of direct argumentation and sometimes very strong criticism bordering on name-calling and finger-pointing.  Scholars and academics are not immune to fighting “dirty” it seems.  Let us, however, do our best to avoid that in our class and be more civilized!

 

Famine, Affluence and Morality – Peter Singer

Singer’s passage begins with a picture of nine million destitute refugees.  He could be talking about any situation, as he mentions later on a footnote on page 919.  In the text on page 919 he says “The Bengal emergency is just the latest and most acute of a series of major emergencies in various parts of the world, arising both from natural and from man-made causes.”  As he notes in the opening pages, governments know what is going on, but provide little funding (he lists amounts in British pounds) in comparison to other projects. 

Singer, throughout his career, has called for governmental and social reform to care for the poor.  He contends that if we have the power to prevent a very bad thing from occurring, and if we can prevent it without "sacrificing anything morally significant," then we have a moral duty to help.According to Singer, giving to famine relief and similar causes is not an act of charity but a stringent moral obligation. 

Singer thinks that we have the same obligation to give to the needy close by AND to those far away.  There is no higher priority to closer neighbors.  This is mentioned at various places in the passage, especially page 920 where Singer says he will not say much about why he does not take “proximity and distance into account.” This is an important point for Singer, and it has been widely criticized, as Timmerman does in the next passage.

On page 921, Singer mentions the idea of a “global village.”  This phrase has become much more popular in recent years, and refers to the fact that the world is “shrinking” due to technological advances.  Singer notes here, again, that there would seem to be “no possible justification for discriminating on geographical grounds.”  So it seems this “global village” provides counter-evidence to any claim that people in a poorer starving nation are too far away to be able to help.

On page 923, Singer mentions an important term: supererogatory.  Generally, supererogatory means to “go above and beyond the call of duty” when applied in ethics.  Singer mentions it here to show that there is a moral obligation to assist those in need.  Giving money to the poor is not supererogatory, he claims, because it would be wrong not to do so.

At the end of the passage, Singer defends philosophers (like himself) who “play a role in public affairs” (pp. 928-9).  Far from being a spectator, Singer has been an active voice and promoter of animal rights, environmental rights and altruistic endeavors to assist in relieving world hunger.  He says that “Discussion, though, is not enough” (p. 929), and he clearly argues for a sacrifice by all affluent people to help all those in need.  It seems we need to decide who is truly “affluent.”

 

A Reply to Singer - Travis Timmerman

Timmerman aims to refute Singer's well-known arguments by claiming that it is unsound because we do not have such stringent duties (p. 930, introduction to this passage).  On page 930, Timmerman lists the steps of the form of Singer's arguments.  Premise two has the phrase "in your power" and I encourage you to carefully think about what is actually in your power or the power of an individual to make actual change.  He later questions the validity, and perhaps the sustainability, of premise two.

Timmerman then proceeds to critically analyze, and criticize, Singer's "drowning child" argument.  Note just how Timmerman argues his case.  Singer seems to think that if a person encountered this  (rather wild) situation, they would interpret it as ahistorical - a one-time occurence that will not be repeated.  However, giving to poorer nations will need to be repeated because the affluent nation will continue to be in a position to help, and therefore should help.  

Timmerman's position is one of caution, he seems to claim.  He proposes, on page 933, that it should be possible for "unlucky Lisa" to enjoy some other good (like going to the theater) in addition to saving as many drowning children as she can - for as long as she can.  Singer's argument is too extreme for Timmerman, as Timmerman seems to imply that the moral necessity of always putting one's self in the position of giving to the maximum effort may just be too great of a burden on actual human beings.

 

Again, I have not provided full details here, so I encourage you to read the texts for themselves – particularly with regard to these possible responses to the massive issue of world hunger.  Which parts seem most useful, valuable, sustainable or the opposites (not useful, not valuable, not sustainable)?  What would you feel comfortable doing if you had opportunities to give significant life-changing (and government-changing) amounts of aid to the poor of the world?

Above all, think critically when reading all of the passages in this chapter.  In my opinion, all of the theories and issues we have studied up until now have helped to prepare the way to discuss this powerful, but hopefully not too overwhelming, issue of world hunger.  

Option 1

Low Cost Option
Download this past answer in few clicks

22.99 USD

PURCHASE SOLUTION

Already member?


Option 2

Custom new solution created by our subject matter experts

GET A QUOTE