Fill This Form To Receive Instant Help

Help in Homework
trustpilot ratings
google ratings


Homework answers / question archive / Topic: Do rich people rather than rich countries bear the greatest responsibility for climate change? My Position is NO

Topic: Do rich people rather than rich countries bear the greatest responsibility for climate change? My Position is NO

Sociology

Topic: Do rich people rather than rich countries bear the greatest responsibility for climate change?

My Position is NO. (Position was assigned, please do not change.)

The position paper should be a minimum of 500 words to a maximum of 1,000 words (about 2 pages). Not more than 1000 words.

You also need give me an outline of the position paper. An example was attached in the Introduction.

I will share you the requirement readings later. I will share you the Introduction about "How to Write a Position Paper" and an example. The rubric will be shared with you.

 Do rich people rather than rich countries bear the greatest responsibility for climate change? Paul G. Harris and Kenneth Shockley Summary of the debate This debate engages with the question of moral responsibility and climate change. We might agree that the rich carry more responsibility for causing the climate to change than do the poor, but is it rich people or rich countries that should be held to greater account? Paul Harris argues that given the huge inequalities within states—both developed and developing—it should be rich individuals who carry the greatest moral responsibility for tackling climate change, although rich states have enormous responsibilities, too. People’s actions cause greenhouse gases to be emitted and the more one emits the greater ones responsibility. Kenneth Shockley challenges this position by arguing that it is nation states that are the appropriate, and more effective, agents for acting to reduce the risks of climate change. Individuals, especially rich individuals, do have some moral responsibility, but primarily it is states who must accept the greater responsibility for climate change and lead the search for solutions. YES: Rich people ought to behave responsibly (before it’s too late) (Paul G. Harris) Introduction Contrary to received wisdom, countries—that is, nation states—do not cause climate change; people do. People are the agents who actually behave in ways that cause climate change. If every country that currently exists were to be dissolved, climate change would continue to grow worse because the agents of change—people—would continue to behave in ways that directly and indirectly emit greenhouse gases (GHGs) that pollute the atmosphere. In contrast, if every citizen of every country were to disappear, climate change would be addressed to the fullest extent possible. The most basic conceptions of fairness and justice, which even children understand, demand that those who are responsible for causing harm should stop doing so. Those who cause the most harm, especially if they do so voluntarily and for relatively trivial reasons, have the greatest responsibility to stop. With few exceptions, the richer the person the more that person consumes and pollutes and thus the greater that person’s adverse environmental impact. What is more, the richer the person the more that person is capable of choosing to behave differently and the more capable that person is to help others to do likewise—and indeed to aid those who suffer the consequences of pollution. Consequently, rich people have disproportionately greater responsibility for climate Responsibility for climate change 147 change and thus disproportionately greater responsibility to stop making the problem worse. As Simon Caney has argued, ‘the burden of dealing with climate change should rest predominantly with the wealthy of the world, by which I mean af?uent persons in the world (not af?uent countries)’ (Caney, 2005: 770). With riches come responsibilities What does it mean to be a rich person? To be rich is to have ‘abundant possessions and material wealth’, with ‘more than enough to gratify normal needs’ (Merriam-Webster Dictionary). By this de?nition, there are well over one billion rich people around the world. The majority of them live in Europe, North America and other parts of the ‘developed’ world, but at least hundreds of millions of them live within ‘developing’ countries (such as Brazil, China and India). Most readers of this book are likely to be rich. Even if you do not have a large amount of money in the bank, if you have more than enough ‘stuff’ to gratify your needs, you are rich, especially when compared to how billions of people continue to live (more than a few of them in rich countries). Cheeseburgers, fast fashion, luxury possessions, energy-hungry homes, private automobiles, cheap air travel and many other manifestations of af?uent ‘western’ lifestyles are, historically speaking, not normal. Neither are they normal if there is any hope of avoiding catastrophic climate change. To put it melodramatically, if every person who is rich by this de?nition were to drop dead tomorrow, the nominal objectives of the Paris Agreement on Climate Change for the next few decades would probably be realised without any additional effort by countries, rich or poor (cf. Chakravarty et al., 2009). Rich people do matter. Naturally, measured individually, super-rich people matter more than ordinarily rich ones; each rich person is responsible for contributing to climate change and each super-rich person is even more responsible (Otto et al., 2019). Nevertheless, nearly all rich people live and consume like never before in human history (and often have one or more children who will do the same throughout their lives). They live well beyond meeting their needs, polluting the atmosphere in the process. Vitally, the number of people living in this way is growing very rapidly around the world. Without discounting the enormous responsibility of rich countries for climate change, putting all of the responsibility on them is a recipe for dangerous climate change. Even if one believes that rich countries deserve to be blamed (as I do), and even if those countries accept this blame (many of them claim that they do), very few of them have acted on this responsibility to anywhere near the extent that is required to slow global warming and other manifestations of climate change. We have far too little to show for blaming rich countries for climate change. Doing so almost exclusively is neither a practical way of attributing responsibility nor the most morally correct way to do so. Waving the ?ag of responsibility: blaming rich countries Before we can settle on the fairest solutions to the problem, and speci?cally who or what ought to take which actions, we need to decide who or what is most responsible. International negotiations and national policy formulation around climate change have been dominated by the mantra that rich countries ought to be taking responsibility. This idea is at the root of the concept of ‘common but differentiated responsibility’ that underlies international negotiations on climate change: while all countries share responsibility, the rich ones 148 Paul G. Harris and Kenneth Shockley deserve most of it, and they therefore ought to be taking action to cut their climate-changing emissions and to help developing countries cope with the consequences of those emissions. This initial focus on countries as the responsible agents was not irrational. Nearly all other global problems—war and peace, economic development and even most transboundary environmental problems—have been dealt with by countries trying to act collectively. They have often done so successfully. What is more, although states are formally only institutional constructs (a state per se does not have any agency; see Chapter 12), most people identify as nationals of a particular country, they need passports to travel very far internationally and there are physical barriers between many countries. But climate change does not recognise political boundaries. Neither the power of the state nor passport controls nor border walls nor anything else yet devised can stop GHG emissions ‘going global’ and affecting almost every community. No country has yet found a way to immunise itself against the effects of climate change. Such a solution does not exist (although for a counter-argument see Chapter 8). As rich and poor countries trade accusations in international negotiations, and national leaders point to other countries’ inaction to combat climate change as justi?cation for their own lack of action (this is precisely the argument used by governments of Australia and the USA), GHG emissions continue to increase. This is happening even as scientists tell us that we need to all but eliminate them very soon (Xu et al., 2018). Despite several decades of negotiations by countries to solve this problem—starting before most of the readers of this book were born—GHG emissions into the atmosphere continue to rise. It is patently obvious that countries have failed to address climate change effectively and there is no indication that this will change anytime soon. Because the world’s responses to climate change have focused on the rights and responsibilities of countries, resulting international agreements and related national policies have largely ignored the rights and responsibilities of people (see Harris, 2016). Aggressive responses to climate change cannot come from continuing on this pathway. Without major and widespread action by rich people very soon, it seems all but inevitable that climate change will be catastrophic, especially for the world’s poor (see Chapter 1). In addition to the unwillingness of rich countries to act responsibly, a problem with the country-focused attribution of responsibility is that it has let rich people largely off the hook, in both practical and moral terms. Blaming rich countries for climate change has made rich people everywhere lazy. They are waiting for rich country governments to do all of the work of fostering action. Rich people can say to themselves, ‘I have paid my taxes and done what my government has demanded of me. I have ful?lled my responsibility’. But this attitude is wrong both practically and morally: it enables people who contribute disproportionately to the problem to pretend that they are not disproportionately responsible to change their related behaviours. It allows them to imagine that the moral duties fall on other actors. And it allows those rich people who live in developing countries—a smaller number than in developed countries, but one that is growing rapidly—to ignore their responsibilities completely. Is it any wonder that there is so little willingness among citizens to embrace the major changes in their lives that are needed to face climate change squarely? A cosmopolitan debate: responsibilities of the most capable people There is an alternative to the assumption that climate change is primarily the responsibility of rich countries. That alternative can be found in cosmopolitanism, the notion that all Responsibility for climate change 149 human beings belong to a single community, based on a shared morality. Cosmopolitanism attributes responsibility (and rights) to persons (as well as other actors). From a cosmopolitan perspective, people are moral agents who should take responsibility for their actions. Cosmopolitans acknowledge the responsibilities of capable people regardless of the countries in which they reside or hold citizenship. While cosmopolitans would not deny the responsibilities of rich countries, neither would they deny the responsibilities of rich people (Harris, 2016). For cosmopolitans, a rich person in Britain is not, prima facie, any more (or less) responsible for climate change than is a rich person in China. From this perspective, rich people ought not wait for rich countries to act on those countries’ responsibilities for climate change. Rich people are responsible to do what they can to mitigate their own contributions to climate change regardless of what rich countries do. Cosmopolitanism is a useful way to debate climate change. It exposes the reality that many millions of rich people around the world remain under little or no legal or even moral obligation to do anything about climate change solely because they do not live within the rich countries that have started to regulate climate damaging behaviours (see Harris, 2016). To blame rich countries for climate change is to not blame millions of the richest people on Earth. For example, from a country-focused perspective, a rich German enjoying a ?ight in her private jet is held indirectly responsible for climate change (but only a little bit, because she is still enjoying the ?ight after all) because her behaviour is taxed by her country’s government as part of its efforts to reduce the country’s (and, technically, also the EU’s) GHG emissions. However, an even richer Brazilian enjoying a ?ight in his own private jet bears no responsibility at all, not even indirectly, because his country is not technically ‘rich’. Similarly, a well-off (but not super-rich) resident of rich Sweden will have his behaviour taxed and regulated to push him to reduce his activities that lead to GHG emissions. In contrast, millions of better-off people (vastly more than the entire population of Sweden) in ‘developing’ China are encouraged by their government to consume and travel to fuel economic growth—to do all of the things in fact that people must stop doing if climate change is to be taken seriously. Cosmopolitanism reveals this absurdity by looking past the political importance of national borders to identify where responsibility ought to be attributed. In doing so, it reveals both the ethical and practical importance of making rich people everywhere responsible for climate change. Even if not all climate policy revolves around what is revealed by this alternative approach, much of it ought to be. All rich people, regardless of whether they live in rich countries, ought not wait for their national governments to force them to change their polluting lifestyles. They should reduce their GHG emissions as far as they can, which effectively means trying to eliminate all non-essential polluting activities from their lives. For example, rich people ought proactively to curtail airline travel because such behaviour contributes substantially to climate change and is almost always not necessary, often done only for pleasure. Rich people ought to curtail their consumption of meat because it is a major source of GHG emissions, is not necessary for health and alternative foods are available to almost all rich people. Rich people ought to have fewer children—unless those children will be nurtured to live their lives sustainably. Rich people should also use their capabilities to push for public policies that foster major cuts in GHG emissions. Rich people in democracies ought to support and vote for candidates who advocate aggressive pro-climate policies. Rich people ought to take such actions not because their countries are responsible for climate change, but because they are as well. To emphasise this point, James Garvey asks us to look in the mirror: ‘It is 150 Paul G. Harris and Kenneth Shockley possible to think that my failure to do something about my high-carbon lifestyle really is morally outrageous’ (Garvey, 2008: 142; cf. Harris, 2016: 151–152). What individual persons do, and of course especially what individual rich persons do, matters because each individual’s contribution to climate-changing pollution is added to that of everyone else’s. As Steve Vanderheiden argues, ‘Isolated individual contributions to larger aggregate problems may appear to be trivial, yet the countless occurrences of such seemingly trivial acts together add up to quite serious harms’ (Vanderheiden, 2008: 166). To use the words of Thomas Pogge, which he applies to the problem of global poverty: ‘nearly every privileged person might say that she bears no responsibility at all because she alone is powerless to bring about a reform of the global order’ (Pogge, 2002: 170). Pogge describes this as ‘an implausible line of argument, entailing as it does that each participant in a massacre is innocent, provided any persons killed would have been killed by others, had he abstained’ (Pogge, 2002: 170). Many will argue that individual rich persons actually do not have power to respond to climate change in meaningful ways. Garvey has a response to such thinking: against the claim that individual choices cannot matter much, is that nothing else about you stands a chance of making a moral difference at all. If anything matters, it’s all those little choices … The only chance you have of making a moral difference consists in the individual choices you make. (Garvey, 2008: 150) Put another way, the total impact of a life lived high on the hog compared to one lived simply adds up and, when multiplied by two billion or more other relatively af?uent people in the world, the impact is gargantuan. It is the difference between a liveable planet for all and truly monumental suffering for billions. (Harris, 2016: 192–193) Thinking more about what rich people do, and less about what rich countries do, helps to highlight these realities. Historical responsibility: the practicality of a paradox Looking at responsibility for climate change from a cosmopolitan perspective has other bene?ts. For example, it enables us to do a better job of assessing historical responsibility for climate change. One obstacle to persuading rich countries to take on more responsibility, and to act accordingly, is differing views on which of them are more or less responsible for GHG emissions in the past. By looking at responsibility from a cosmopolitan perspective, one might see that there could be more responsibility among rich people in developing countries than normal country-oriented arguments might reveal. This is because rich people in af?uent countries did not realise that they were causing climate change until the latter years of the last century. When they realised the consequences of what they were doing, they were already deeply immersed in lifestyles that lead to severe climate change. In contrast, rich people in many developing countries who adopted similar lifestyles only recently, including the many millions of new middle-class consumers in those Responsibility for climate change 151 countries, knew from the time that they became ‘rich’ that many of their consumption behaviours were contributing to climate change. They were aware of climate change before getting on the global consumption bandwagon and with that awareness comes responsibility. History may not judge them favourably. (We can debate whether ordinary citizens fully understand their own contribution to climate change, but we ought not overlook wilful ignorance among most rich people.) Considering such a paradoxical conclusion is only possible if we stop focusing so much on rich countries and instead focus more on rich people, including those who do not live in rich countries. For example, the number of Chinese tourists is growing rapidly, helping to make air travel one of the fastest-growing sources of climate-changing emissions. Millions of Chinese citizens now ?y around the world on holidays, contributing greatly to climate change. If we attribute responsibility for climate change to rich countries, all of these holidaymakers bear no responsibility for the contribution that they make to climate change because China (despite its obvious wealth) is still of?cially ‘developing’. Those Chinese tourists can and do make the argument that they have a right to consume in this way because China does not bear responsibility and that it has the right to follow the same development path as that of the world’s rich countries (see Harris, 2011). Debating climate change from a cosmopolitan perspective could lead to better policies for and by countries. In addition to doing what is morally right, assuming more responsibility for climate change by rich people—even those not living in rich countries—could help to nudge rich countries to do more to live up to their responsibilities for climate change. For example, if rich people outside rich countries are not held responsible for climate change, rich people within rich countries—most of which are democracies, where rich people have signi?cant in?uence on policymaking—will do all that they can to discourage their governments from implementing policies that hold the rich suf?ciently responsible. This is more or less what has been happening for decades, with the consequence being very few new policies that result in major cuts in people’s GHG emissions. (Has any rich person in any rich country avoided air travel due to a government policy discouraging such behaviour?) It would be much harder for rich people in rich countries to justify such responses to climate change if rich people all around the world were made proportionately responsible. What is more, if not-so-rich people in rich countries were to see the richest among them ?nally taking responsibility and acting accordingly, widespread political opposition to major action on climate change would be diminished. Conclusion We can argue that rich people have the greatest responsibility for climate change because they cause so much harm and are so capable of stopping that harm. But, in truth, they are not solely responsible. Rich countries, too, are responsible—as are all capable actors, ranging from community groups and businesses to multinational corporations and substate actors, such as Scotland and New York City, as well as international governmental and nongovernmental organisations, such as the European Union and the Fédération Internationale de Football Association (FIFA). Collectively, all of them are responsible for climate change (see Chapter 12). Collectively, all actors that are rich have a responsibility to change their ways. However, after three decades of effort, we should stop relying so heavily on countries to do that which they are not well designed to do: to act for the long-term global 152 Paul G. Harris and Kenneth Shockley collective good instead of for their own perceived short-term national interests (which, by the way, are often shaped to protect the interests of their most af?uential citizens). While we ought not ignore the responsibilities of rich countries, we also ought not ignore the responsibilities of rich people. More of the climate change debate should be about them. More policies should be about them. More education should be about their responsibilities—about your responsibilities, and mine. And we should debate the fact that millions of the world’s rich people live in developing countries. Regardless of what those countries are willing and able to do to address climate change, their rich citizens ought not be let off the hook. To do so sends the worst message to rich people in rich countries. Telling the latter to bear fewer children, ?y less, drive less, eat less meat, live in smaller homes, use less energy and consume less, will not be nearly as effective a message if they see rich people in developing countries ?ying more, eating more meat and so on. This goes without saying, but we ought to start saying it much more. Again, rich people matter—everywhere. Acknowledgements The author has made similar arguments in Harris (2013, 2016) and in other publications, which are listed on his website: www.paulgharris.net. NO: Primary responsibility must rest with states and institutional actors (Kenneth Shockley) Introduction: what is moral responsibility? Rich people do not bear the greatest responsibility for climate change. Primary responsibility falls on states, provincial and other regional governments, international corporations, ?nancial institutions, intergovernmental organisations and other actors in the international arena. In what follows I will refer to these entities as institutional actors, in contrast to individual actors. Institutional actors are able to bring about change, are the primary drivers for the climate change that has taken place and are the primary means by which it can be addressed. Whether we think of responsibility as retrospective (the responsibility we hold for what we have done historically) or prospective (the responsibility we hold for what we can do), the responsible party must be a causally effective agent. And in the international arena where responsibility for climate change can be meaningfully addressed, individuals are simply not effective agents. The argument is straightforward: if something is not an effective agent, then it cannot be morally responsible. First, rich people, collectively, do not constitute an agent, and so do not constitute an effective agent. Second, a rich person as an individual does not have suf?cient causal control over climate change and so does not constitute an effective agent, at least in relation to climate change. As moral responsibility requires some degree of causal control on the part of a responsible agent, rich people are not morally responsible for climate change … at least not directly. We should be clear on what is necessary to be held responsible.1 Whether a matter of being held responsible for what we have done in the past or what we are required to do going forward, moral responsibility requires both causal connection and blameworthiness. The ?rst element, causal connection, is the requirement that to be retrospectively responsible for something one must have done it, and to be prospectively responsible for something one Responsibility for climate change 153 must be able to do it. On most accounts of responsibility there must be some causal connection between an agent’s performance of an action and any responsibility attributed to that agent for the action or state of affairs that results from that action. For example, suppose an anvil falls off a building and hits Abbas on the head. If Beta neither caused the anvil to fall (say, by pushing it), nor could have prevented the anvil from falling (say, because she lacked the strength), it would be odd to say that Beta is either retrospectively or prospectively morally responsible for what happened to Abbas. Moral responsibility requires a degree of causal control suf?cient to make an individual an effective agent. Unless an individual is causally effective, they cannot be morally responsible. The second element, blameworthiness, amounts to the claim that there was something culpable about what was done (e.g. it was done recklessly) or the way it was done (e.g. it was done with malicious intent), or what should be done (as a duty of one’s social station or as compensation for a historical bene?t or historical transgression). But note, there is an important asymmetry between causal control and blameworthiness. In order to be blameworthy for an action or outcome one must have some causal connection to the action or outcome. It isn’t appropriate to blame someone for an action, to hold them responsible for it, when they neither performed that action (they didn’t do it) nor could have prevented it. Causation is required before we can consider blame. For example, even if someone steps on my toe (and so has the requisite causal connection), they are only blameworthy for stepping on my toe if they did it intentionally, or if it occurred because they were negligent and failed to exercise due care, or could and should have taken measures to avoid stepping on my toe. The acid test for blameworthiness is whether or not the relevant party had mens rea, a guilty mind. We will return to blameworthiness in the discussion below but, here, we should see the central importance of causal control for responsibility. Rich people, responsibility and e?ective agency While in aggregate rich people have had a disproportionate in?uence on the climate, they are individually not effective agents and, in aggregate, not agents at all. First, once we are clear about the signi?cance of causal control for matters of moral responsibility, it should be equally clear that individual agents are not individually responsible for climate change (SinnottArmstrong, 2005). It is certainly the case that a very small percentage of the world’s population engage in activities that produce a disproportionate share of emissions (Shue, 1993). With very few exceptions, however, only states and other international actors have the requisite causal control over emissions and so only states and other international actors are, therefore, responsible. Particular rich individuals are generally not effective agents of change either for addressing future challenges generated by climate change or for taking historical responsibility for climate change. Moreover, exceptions help make the case. Some very few wealthy or politically powerful individuals do have what we might think of as international agency, including the Pope, Bill Gates, Jeff Bezos and others. But they usually have this agency only through institutional actors (the Church, international corporations and so on). This connection between individuals and institutions will be important in what follows. Second, rich people are not collectively responsible for climate change as they are not the sort of group that is or could be a collective agent. We should be clear on what would be required for ‘rich people’ to be an agent. Following List and Pettit (2011: 158), a group is morally responsible if they are able, as a group, (1) to face a ‘normatively signi?cant choice’ that involves performing an action that is right or wrong, or good or bad, (2) to understand that choice in such a way that they can evaluate options and make a ‘normative 154 Paul G. Harris and Kenneth Shockley judgement about the options,’ and (3) to have ‘the control required for choosing between the options’. The key point is that for the group to be held responsible it will have to have the capacity for deliberation and control necessary for any agent. Rich people, taken as a single group, are simply not the right sort of entity. All rich individuals, taken together, do not share the deliberative or decision-making processes or institutions necessary for attributing agency. There is no collective understanding, evaluation, judgement or control. There is no capacity for collective choice. Therefore, as a group, rich people do not constitute an agent of the relevant sort to hold either backward directed responsibility for historical harms or forward directed responsibility for making the necessary changes. But this doesn’t get rich people off the hook (see Moellendorf, 2014). Individuals, particularly rich individuals, are not morally free to do whatever they like, thereby of?oading moral responsibility to institutional actors. They have responsibilities, but those responsibilities are ?ltered, indirectly, through states and other institutional actors. States and institutions are the appropriate focus for responsibility In contrast with rich individuals, institutional actors are effective agents in the international arena (see List and Pettit, 2011, for an argument that institutional entities may constitute agents). States are able to affect domestic policy by, for example, addressing consumption patterns and enabling individual actors to have effective choices involving greenhouse gas emissions. They are able to affect the international political context in a way conducive to addressing climate change. Other non-state institutional actors— banks, international political entities, provincial and other regional governments—also have the capacity to make similar changes in both the domestic and international political landscape (see Chapter 12). Decisions made by banks to support renewable energy resources, long-term infrastructure decisions made by local and regional governments and regional carbon trading markets (see Chapter 6), for example, all have the capacity to make substantial changes to emissions patterns. Decisions by particular rich individuals usually have little or no effect on such patterns, except insofar as they leverage institutions. Not only are institutional actors (and remember, institutional actors include much more than traditional nation states) the relevant actors for addressing global environmental problems such as climate change, they are also the only means by which any particular individual could have any relevant effect in the international political realm. Institutional actors are the mediators between individual choice and global change. And they are political actors. They can make a difference in how we address climate change; they can change the political landscape, both domestic and international, in which serious efforts to address climate change take place. Moreover, they are the entities that have failed to make the necessary changes, historically, that have put us in the place we are in. Primary responsibility for climate change rests with institutional actors. They hold and have held the levers to make the needed changes. There is this important complication. As the concern is often about the moral responsibility associated with climate change, individuals might yet play a particularly signi?cant role. We have seen that moral responsibility requires that the responsible entity have something akin to a guilty mind. This is challenging to see in the case of states and other institutional actors (although, again, see List and Pettit, 2011). Further, while it is unclear how rich people, taken as a group, could possibly have a guilty mind, it is quite clear that individual persons, rich or not, are more than capable of having a guilty mind. Responsibility for climate change 155 Individuals are the ultimate example of moral agents. However, as we have noted, individuals are not causally connected to climate change in the right way and so do not bear (individual) moral responsibility for climate change (Jamieson, 1992). But individuals might well bear moral responsibility for failing to contribute to institutions in the right way (Gardiner, 2017; Shockley, 2016). For that is a matter over which they do have some control and a matter which may well have great moral signi?cance. What role should be played by the rich, or by individuals more generally? Individuals do have a role to play, one that comes with substantial moral responsibility. In particular, rich individuals have bene?tted the most from our unsustainable economic system, have had a disproportionate in?uence on the institutions that can have an effect on climate change and there are some who have a large amount of political in?uence. Rich individuals are therefore responsible for contributing to changes in institutional actors such that those institutional actors are better able to address climate change. With the great power that (rightly or wrongly) comes from bene?tting from the economic systems that generate climate change comes great responsibility. The industrial processes and economic growth that have fuelled climate change have made the rich rich. And so one might think there is a prima facie responsibility for providing some sort of compensation for the climate change associated with this wealth. However, focusing on this wealth may well lead us to miss the underlying cause—the institutional arrangements and economic and political systems—that enabled the development of individual wealth in the ?rst place. If there is a responsibility on wealthy individuals for changing these arrangements and systems, then the greater the ability to make such changes, the greater the responsibility for doing so. The historical acquisition of power by rich individuals generates a responsibility to rectify wrongs—by changing the system that led to those wrongs. It also places a responsibility on them for making the forward directed changes that address the problems that will arise from climate change and to make the institutional changes necessary to minimise the generation of further harm. Because wealth provides the means to make the institutional changes that can have an effect on climate change, wealthy individuals have a responsibility to do so. Yet one might worry that individuals will not live up to their responsibilities and make the necessary changes in their political and institutional environment. Getting individuals to live up to their responsibilities is clearly a problem, but it is a familiar one. The alternative, requiring individuals to satisfy direct cosmopolitan responsibilities for climate change—as argued here by Paul Harris—would seem to face a substantially worse version of this challenge. As Jamieson (1992) and Sinnott-Armstrong (2005) both make clear, it is very hard to operationalise, or even to make sense of, an individual responsibility for climate change, particularly a moral responsibility. In such contexts it is very dif?cult to see how any individual could be both blameworthy and causally connected to any relevant harm. Individuals may have dif?culties living up to their well-established responsibilities. But it is much harder to see how individuals would live up to new and unfamiliar responsibilities they can’t even understand. There is more hope in getting individuals to live up to their responsibilities through a contributory approach. So, while the possession of economic and political power by rich people does bring with it some responsibility to drive institutional actors to change their behaviour, that responsibility is not for climate change directly. At least in most instances, individual responsibility is for making the changes (and having failed to make the changes in the 156 Paul G. Harris and Kenneth Shockley past) to our political systems and the related economic and social institutions. We might well think of this form of individual moral responsibility as contributory responsibility. We will see below that this is important if we are to assess responsibility properly and bring about effective change: both institutions and individuals have roles to play. Conclusion There is a practical tension underlying the question of who bears primary responsibility for climate change. If primary responsibility is focused on rich individuals, we risk letting states off the hook. If states are not responsible, and rich individuals are, then there is no point in pressing states to address climate change. This echoes a common concern with the renewed focus on non-state actors in the climate change policy process (see Chapter 12)—provincial and regional governments, banks, nongovernmental organisations, research entities and so on. Some worry that states might reason that if these actors can play a larger role, then perhaps states can take a smaller role. They might thereby avoid having to address any historical responsibility or duties due to their citizens or to those affected by their historical actions. On the other hand, if primary responsibility is focused on states, we risk letting individuals, especially rich individuals, off the hook from making any individual changes. Individuals, it might be thought, can do whatever they want and pass the buck on to the institutions and governments that hold responsibility. Of course, given the history of state inaction with regard to climate change, cynicism about states’ ability to address climate change is understandable. Harris (2008: 482) writes, ‘the climate change regime has failed. The arguments for international—that is, interstate—justice that have permeated the climate change regime have been insuf?cient’. His thought is that while we should still rely on states, we need to rely on individuals as well. To be sure, policy institutions (normally states) ought to play a big part by mediating the obligations of individual persons. However, institutions have failed so far; climate change is accelerating. We ought not reject the argument, made by some cosmopolitans, that people ought to push for the creation of the institutions that can mediate our obligations (Moellendorf, 2002). But we must be realistic in admitting the dif?culty of doing this: we have not succeeded in doing it so far, we cannot wait forever, and huge numbers of people live in authoritarian environments where they have little ability to shape institutions, although they do often have the ability to shape their own behaviour. (Harris, 2008: 490) Yet to think that individuals, acting through their reduced consumption, can affect change in the climate is at least as problematic as thinking states will solve all our climate problems for us. What I propose here is a middle ground: states and institutions bear primary responsibility, but individuals bear a contributory responsibility, a responsibility to ensure that those states and institutional actors are doing the job they are morally required to do (Shockley, 2016). One of the great challenges of climate change is the dangerous decoupling of moral and causal responsibility, of both forward and backward directed varieties. Focusing on either individual responsibility, in order to capture the distinctively moral features of Responsibility for climate change 157 responsibility, or institutional responsibility, in order to capture the need for ef?cacious responsibilities, misses something. Contributory responsibility carries a distinctively moral connection between individual responsibility and the institutions that are effective climate actors in the international arena. It therefore provides a means of binding individuals to the moral harms of climate change, without requiring institutional actors to have moral responsibilities they cannot have or requiring individuals to do more than they are able. While the rich do not hold primary responsibility for climate change, we all have a responsibility to create and change the institutional actors that are the effective, responsible parties in our global response to climate change. To the extent that the rich are more able to bring about change in those institutions, they have a greater responsibility to do so. Individuals have a better chance of leveraging institutions—states, ?nancial institutions, NGOs—to thereby make the changes necessary to lead to less climate-intensive consumption. This is the contrast: no one should doubt that individuals have moral responsibilities resulting from the grossly problematic actions of states. The question is what they have responsibilities for. As individuals are ineffective actors in the international arena where climate change can be affected, they cannot be responsible for making those changes. Ought implies can, after all. But coordinated individuals, individuals in concert, organised by institutions and governments that they themselves reform or develop, are able to make the changes necessary to reduce emissions. And, if they are successful, to also reform the institutions and social arrangements that make climate change so deeply problematic. If we want to address the cause of climate change we should look not to individuals, whether rich or not. Rather, we should look to the states and other institutions that are both the effective actors and mediators of individual actions. Primary responsibility for addressing climate change rests with those entities, even if it is the moral responsibility of individuals to change those entities so that they better address the greatest moral challenge of our day. Further reading Broome, J. (2012) Climate Matters: Ethics in a Warming World. New York: WW Norton & Company. In this book, Broome considers the moral dimensions of climate change, reasoning through what universal standards of goodness and justice require of us, both as citizens and as governments. His conclusions both challenge and enlighten. Eco-conscious readers hear they have a duty to offset all their carbon emissions, while policymakers are called upon to grapple with what, if anything, is owed to future generations. Gardiner, S.M. and Weisbach, D.A. (2016) Debating Climate Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. This book presents arguments for and against the relevance of ethics to global climate policy. Gardiner argues that climate change is fundamentally an ethical issue, since it is an early instance of a distinctive challenge to ethical action. Ethical concerns are at the heart of many of the decisions that need to be made. By contrast, Weisbach argues that existing ethical theories are not well suited to addressing climate change. Harris, P.G. (2016) Global Ethics and Climate Change. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. This book combines the science of climate change with ethical critique. Harris exposes the increasing intensity of dangerous trends—particularly growing global af?uence, material consumption and pollution—and the intensifying moral dimensions of changes to the environment. A free learning guide 158 Paul G. Harris and Kenneth Shockley is available at: www.edinburghuniversitypress.com/media/resources/Global_Ethics_and_Climate_ Change_2nd_Edition_-_Learning_Guide.pdf Hayward, T. (2012) Climate change and ethics. Nature Climate Change. 2(12): 843–848. Hayward shows how the greater part of debate about the ethics of climate change focuses on questions about who has what responsibility to bear the burdens of mitigating it or adapting to it. The connections between human rights and climate change are examined, as too are questions concerning justice in the present, our responsibilities to the future and the relation between individual and collective responsibilities. Peeters, W., Smet, A.D., Diependaele, L., Sterckx, S., McNeal, R.H. and De Smet, A. (2015) Climate Change and Individual Responsibility: Agency, Moral Disengagement and the Motivational Gap. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. This book discusses the agency and responsibility of individuals for climate change. It argues that these responsibilities are underemphasised, enabling individuals to maintain their consumptive lifestyles without having to accept moral responsibility for their luxury emissions. Follow-up questions for use in student classes 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. If rich countries fail to act on their responsibilities for climate change, which actors should do so instead? Why and how should those actors do it and why have they not done so already? Would the responsibility of rich countries for climate change be different if all of their rich citizens moved to developing countries and took up citizenship there? What level of wealth constitutes being rich enough to have a responsibility for changing political institutions capable of addressing climate change? How effective are rich persons as agents of change? What is your responsibility for causing climate change? What is your responsibility for trying to stop it? Note 1 See also Moellendorf (2014: 152–180) for an excellent treatment of responsibility in the context of climate change. References Caney, S. (2005) Cosmopolitan justice, responsibility, and climate change. Leiden Journal of International Law. 18: 747–775. Chakravarty, S., Chikkatur, A., de Coninck, H., Pacala, S., Socolow, R. and Tavoni, M. (2009) Sharing global CO2 emission reductions among one billion high emitters. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 106(29): 11884–11888. Gardiner, S. (2017). Accepting collective responsibility for the future. Journal of Practical Ethics. 5 (1): 22–52. Garvey, J. (2008) The Ethics of Climate Change: Right and Wrong in a Warming World. London: Continuum. Harris, P.G. (2008) Climate change and global citizenship. Law and Policy. 30(4): 481–501. Harris, P.G., ed. (2011) China’s Responsibility for Climate Change: Ethics, Fairness and Environmental Policy. Bristol: Bristol University Press/Policy Press. Harris, P.G. (2013) What’s Wrong with Climate Politics and How to Fix It. Cambridge: Polity. Harris, P.G. (2016) Global Ethics and Climate Change. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Responsibility for climate change 159 Jamieson, D. (1992) Ethics, public policy, and global warming. Science, Technology, and Human Values. 17(2): 139–153. List, C. and Pettit, P. (2011) Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. New York: Oxford University Press. Moellendorf, D. (2002) Cosmopolitan Justice. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Moellendorf, D. (2014) The Moral Challenge of Dangerous Climate Change. New York: Cambridge University Press. Otto, I.M., Kim, K.M., Dubrovksy, N. and Lucht, W. (2019) Shift the focus from the super-poor to the super-rich. Nature Climate Change. 9(2): 82–84. Pogge, T. (2002) Human rights and human responsibilities. In P. De Grieff and C. Cronin, eds. Global Justice and Transnational Politics: Essays on the Moral and Political Challenges of Globalization. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. pp. 151–196. Shockley, K. (2016). Individual and contributory responsibility for environmental harm. In A. Thompson and S. Gardiner, eds. The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 265–275. Shue, H. (1993) Subsistence emissions and luxury emissions. Law and Policy. 15(1): 39–59. Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2005) It’s not my fault: global warming and individual moral obligations. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong and R. Howarth, eds. Perspectives on Climate Change: Science, Economics, Politics, Ethics. Amsterdam: Elsevier. pp. 285–307. Vanderheiden, S. (2008) Atmospheric Justice: A Political Theory of Climate Change. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Xu, Y., Ramanathan, V. and Victor, D.G. (2018) Global warming will happen faster than we think. Nature. 564: 30–32. What is a position paper? A position paper: • • • • is persuasive asserts an arguable claim explains both sides of a controversy uses reasoning and evidence to support a claim Like a debate, a position paper presents one side of an arguable opinion about an issue. The goal of a position paper is to convince the audience that your opinion is valid and defensible. Your job is to take one side of the argument and persuade your audience by demonstrating a well-founded knowledge of the topic being presented, supporting your argument with evidence to ensure the validity of your claims, and refuting the counterclaims to show that you are well informed about both sides. Your audience for this work is your Professor, your course assistant and your fellow students. Unlike debates, a position paper is not about “winning” In a position paper, we often say that you “argue” for a side. The word “argument” can bring up images of hostility or polarization. When people behave like this, they really aren't arguing. They are quarreling. And when people quarrel, they are no longer listening to or considering each other's ideas. An argument is something quite different. Arguments involve making reasonable claims and then backing up those claims with evidence and support. In this class, the objective is not to “win” or prove that you are right and others are wrong. Instead, your primary goal is to show others that you are probably right or that your beliefs are reasonable and worthy of their honest consideration. When possible, we aim to reach an agreement or compromise. Arguments are about getting things done by gaining the cooperation of others. In most situations, an argument is about agreeing as much as disagreeing, about cooperating with others as much as competing with them. Your ability to argue effectively will be an important part of your success in your college courses, your social life, and your career. Analyzing an Issue and Developing an Argument 1. Focusing your position: While your position paper needs to be responsive to the themes discussed in the textbook, you should scope your paper to elaborate one or two of the points that were raised in support of that position that are of the most interest to you. You will need to iterate between focusing your position, background reading and organizing your arguments several times! Deciding on a thesis does not come first. Your position is the result of a thinking process. You may start with a “working” position that you can then modify as you collect and organize the evidence. After the initial exploration of the question at hand, you will continue to refine the "working thesis" to reflect the argument that you think will make sense of the evidence. Here is an example of a weak and a strong position statement: Weak: Only qualified police officers should be allowed to carry weapons on campus. Stronger: Only qualified police officers should be allowed to carry weapons on campus, because the dangers of allowing students and faculty to carry weapons clearly outweigh the slight chance that a concealed weapon would be used in self-defense. 2. Do some background reading to ensure that your position is well supported. Once you are assigned your position, you should do some research on the subject matter. First, read and reread the papers in the textbook. Second, identify a minimum of two external references: one in support of the “yes” and one in support of the “no” position in the text. These references must be entered into the database as well as used to support your position paper. All references that that you include your position paper need to be entered into the database. See the separate instructions. Supporting evidence includes the following: Type of Information Type of Source How to find these sources introductory information and overviews directories, encyclopedias, handbooks Use the Library catalogue in-depth studies books, government reports Library catalogue, Government web sites scholarly articles academic journals Article indexes current issues, opinion pieces newspapers, magazines, blogs, videos, newsreports Article indexes, web sites position papers and analyses association and institute reports Library catalogue, web sites Many of these sources can be located online through the library catalogue and electronic databases, or on the Web. In almost all cases, the expectation is that these sources are available electronically and you will include a URL in the database. You do not have to use all of these types of supporting evidence in your papers. This is simply a list of the various options available to you. Note, however, that your sources may be of differing quality and that every source has some degree of bias (and some much more than others)! Consider the source when incorporating it into your own work. If you have any concerns, speak with your course assistant. 3. Organize the evidence The key to organizing an argument is to remember that you need to treat all major sides of the issue fairly and thoroughly. There are many ways to do this. One suggestion is that you develop a list of the pro and con sides of the topic. This will help you examine your ability to support your counterclaims, along with a list of supporting evidence for both sides. Once you have made your pro and con lists, compare the information side by side with the goal of identifying the claim and counterclaim. You may then select a subset of the key arguments in favor and against your position to develop further. You can select these arguments for a range of reasons, including the ones that you judge to the strongest or most compelling, the most frequently encountered in your research, and the most in need of being “corrected” or troubling. 4. Develop an outline of the arguments and the supporting evidence before you write your full paper Before you start writing, develop an outline that includes each of the items in the checklist below. This will help you focus your arguments. 5. Finally, write your position paper! Here, you can find the organization of the paper and an example of an outline to a full position paper. Organization of the position paper Here is a proposed outline (and checklist) for your position paper. While you have room to be creative in the presentation of your position paper, following this recommended outline ensures that your paper contains all the necessary elements of an excellent position paper. Also, in the outline below, I recommend that you first present the counterarguments and then your own arguments. However, you may prefer to present your arguments first and then the counterarguments or present each argument with its counterargument in turn. Any of these three approaches is acceptable. Introduction: Your introduction has a dual purpose: to indicate both the topic and your position, and to arouse your reader’s interest in what you have to say. ___Introduce the topic and provide background: Catch your readers’ attention! ___Explain why well-meaning people are disagreeing: What are the various positions on this issue? ___Clearly present your side of the issue: Be as specific as possible. This typically appears at the end of your introduction. Counter Argument: You can generate counterarguments by asking yourself what someone who disagrees with you might say about each of the points you've made or about your position as a whole. Once you have thought up some counterarguments, consider how you will respond to them--will you concede that your opponent has a point but explain why your audience should nonetheless accept your argument? Will you reject the counterargument and explain why it is mistaken? Either way, you will want to leave your reader with a sense that your argument is stronger than opposing arguments. ___Summarize the counterclaims ___Provide supporting information for counterclaims ___Refute the counterclaims ___Provide support/proof using one or more references When you are summarizing opposing arguments, be charitable. Present each argument fairly and objectively, rather than trying to make it look foolish. You want to show that you have seriously considered the many sides of the issue, and that you are not simply attacking or mocking your opponents. Because you want to highlight these limitations as fairly as possible, this is not the place to be sarcastic or dismissive. You want to point out the weaknesses in your opponents' argument in a straightforward way. It is usually better to consider one or two serious counterarguments in some depth, rather than to give a long but superficial list of many different counterarguments and replies. There are some additional notes on counter arguments below. Your Argument: You will formulate two to three arguments in support of your position. These will be the positions that you identified from organizing the evidence. You may more points to your argument, but you should not have fewer. For each point of your claim, you will: _____Clearly state your educated and informed opinion _____Provide support/proof using one or more references Now it’s your turn. Explain your side of the argument by walking your readers through the two to three major points of contention, showing them why your side of the argument is stronger. Here is where you need to use your sources to back up your argument. You must use good reasoning, examples, facts, and data to show readers why your opinion is more credible. Your goal is to show your readers that your view is stronger on balance. In other words, both sides probably have their strengths and weaknesses. You want to show that your side has more strengths and fewer weaknesses than the opposing side. Conclusion: The simplest and most basic conclusion is one that restates the thesis in different words and then discusses its implications. ___Restate your argument ___Provide a plan of action (but do not introduce new information) Bring your argument to a close by stating or restating your thesis and looking to the future. Here is where you should drive home your main point or thesis by telling your readers exactly what you believe. Then show how your position leads to a better outcome. Overall, your conclusion should be brief (a paragraph in most arguments). The following is an example of the outline of a position paper written by a student, following the outline provided above. OUTLINE Issue: SHOULD RELATIVELY AFFLUENT PEOPLE HELP THE POOR? I. Thesis: People who are relatively affluent should give a certain fair percentage of their earnings to help reduce absolute poverty on a global level. II. Definitions: Relatively Affluent: rich or wealthy. Fair percentage: a small helpful percentage of earnings, such as ten percent (Peter Singer) Absolute poverty: A condition of life so characterized by malnutrition, illiteracy, disease, squalid surroundings, high infant mortality and low life expectancy that it is beneath any reasonable definition of human decency (Robert McNamara). III. The counterclaim: Wealthy people should not have to help those who are needier unless they choose to do so. A. The strongest support for this claim is that by helping the poor, wealthier people would be increasing the world's population by contributing to the increased survival rates of those who would otherwise have a relatively low life expectancy, thus increasing the rate at which natural resources are consumed and environmental problems will arise. B. Another reason supporting the counterclaim is that just because affluent people have a relatively higher income than others, does not make them morally responsible for those who are not. IV. Argument: A. People who are relatively affluent should give a fair percentage of their earnings to help reduce absolute poverty on a global level. B. It is not the case that helping the poor would necessarily increase population and thus deepen the environmental crisis. i. ii. iii. Monetary aid could bring medical supplies and food, but it could also bring with it contraceptive devices so that people in absolute poverty, who would have begun to see increased life spans, could decrease their birth rates. Helping to reduce absolute poverty would also bring about more people who would be in a position, economically, socially, and medically, to contribute to cleaning up environmental problems and helping solve them. People are resources too and to allow them to live in absolute poverty is to spoil and deplete that resource. C. Animals, which are an important resource and part of life in most parts of the world, are often in more favorable and desirable surroundings than those of places struck by absolute poverty. Therefore, people should be treated with more respect and consideration by being given the chance to live in better surroundings than those afforded to animal resources. D. Killing another human being is morally wrong. Would it not then also be morally wrong to allow someone to die, knowing that they are in surroundings so squalid that they contribute to death? By not acting in favor of eliminating those harmful surroundings, a person would be a contributor to the problems of those people, by simply not acting at all. Therefore, it should be a moral responsibility of those with relative affluence to care for those in absolute poverty. V. In conclusion, affluent people should give a certain percentage of their wealth to help do away with the absolute poverty in the world because people are not only living beings who should not be allowed to live in such squalor, but also because they are an important resource which should not be allowed to waste away. POSITION PAPER SHOULD RELATIVELY AFFLUENT PEOPLE HELP THE POOR? As the world approaches the end of the twentieth century, the gap between rich and poor has never been wider. While some people have more money than it is possible to spend in a lifetime, no matter how lavishly they might make purchases, others are not able to provide even for their most basic needs. On all the continents of the world, people starve to death for lack offood, freeze to death for lack of shelter, die of diseases that could be prevented The situation raises the issue of whether the affluent people of the world have a moral obligation to help the poor. I shall argue that people who are relatively affluent should give a certain fair percentage of their earnings to help reduce absolute poverty on a global scale. My claim is that those who are relatively affluent, that is, people who would normally be defined as rich or wealthy in the context of a given society, have an obligation to give up a small but helpful percentage of their earnings; Peter Singer, an Australian philosopher, suggests ten percent The money would be used to alleviate absolute poverty, a condition that Robert McNamara, the former president of the World Bank, defines as "characterized by malnutrition, illiteracy, disease, squalid surroundings, high infant morality and low life expectancy that is beneath any reasonable definition of human decency. " Many people argue that wealthy people should not have to help those who are needier than they, unless they choose to do so. The strongest argument for this claim is articulated by Garrett Hardin, an ecologist from the University of Southern California. He points to the harmful results of helping people, claiming that by contributing to the increased survival rates of those who would otherwise have a relatively low life expectancy, wealthier people would increase the world's population and thus increase the rate at which natural resources are consumed and environmental problem arise. Although starvation is an evil, Hardin says, helping the poor would create an even greater evil-increased numbers of starving people and fewer resources to help them. Others argue that just because affluent people have a relatively higher income than others, it does not follow that they are morally responsible for those who do not. I believe, in contrast, that people do have a moral obligation to help the desperately poor. For several reasons, it is not the case that helping the poor would necessarily increase population and thus increase environmental degradation. First, while monetary aid could bring medical supplies and food and thus increase population, it could also bring contraceptive devices and increased education about population control. And so, helping the poor could actually decrease the rate of population growth and, in the end, save environmental resources. Secondly, helping to reduce absolute poverty would also bring about more people who would be in a position economically, socially, and medically--to contribute to cleaning up environmental problems and helping solve overpopulation problems. Finally, from a purely practical point of view, it is important to note that people are an economic resource at least as important as firewood and fertile soil, and to allow people to sicken and die is to spoil and waste that resource. The obligation to help the poor is, to a certain extent, simply a matter of human rights. We believe that our pets have a right to decent treatment-enough food to live, shelter from the cold, medical care when they are hurt or ill, and affluent people in America spend large amounts of income to provide for these basic needs for animals. If animals have these rights, then surely humans have at least the same basic rights. People should be treated with more respect and consideration than animals, by being given the chance to live in better surroundings than those afforded to animals. However, the primary reason why the affluent have an obligation to help the poor has to do with the moral principle that killing another human being is wrong. If it is wrong to kill another person, then it is also morally wrong to allow someone to die, when you know they are going to die otherwise, and when it is within your means to save their lives at relatively little cost to yourself By not acting to reduce the harmful, lethal effects of poverty on the world's poor, affluent people are violating a primary moral principle. Therefore, it is a moral responsibility of the rich to help the poor. In conclusion, affluent people should give a certain percentage of their wealth to help do away with absolute poverty in the world, because people are not only living beings who have a right to decent lives, but because it is wrong to allow people to die when helping them live is well within your means. Writing with style and clarity Although the content is important, it will not mean much if the reader can’t understand what you are trying to say. You may have some great ideas in your paper but if you cannot effectively communicate them, you will not receive a very good mark. Keep the following in mind when writing your paper: Diction: Diction refers to the choice of words for the expression of ideas; the construction, disposition, and application of words in your essay, with regard to clearness, accuracy, variety, etc.; mode of expression; and language. There is often a tendency for students to use fancy words and extravagant images in hopes that it will make them sound more intelligent when in fact the result is a confusing mess. Although this approach can sometimes be effective, it is advisable that you choose clear words and be as precise in the expression of your ideas as possible. Paragraphs: Creating clear paragraphs is essential. Paragraphs come in so many sizes and patterns that no single formula could possibly cover them all. The two basic principles to remember are these: a. A paragraph is a means of developing and framing an idea or impression. A a general rule, you should address only one major idea per paragraph. b. The divisions between paragraphs aren’t random, but indicate a shift in focus. In other words you must carefully and clearly organize the order of your paragraphs so that they are logically positioned throughout your paper. Transitions will help you with this. Transitions: In this position paper, your goal is to convey information clearly and concisely, if not to convert the reader to your way of thinking. Transitions help you to achieve these goals by establishing logical connections between sentences, paragraphs, and sections of your papers. In other words, transitions tell readers what to do with the information you present them. Whether single words, quick phrases or full sentences, they function as signs for readers that tell them how to think about, organize, and react to old and new ideas as they read through what you have written. Transitions signal relationships between ideas. Basically, transitions provide the reader with directions for how to piece together your ideas into a logically coherent argument. They are words with particular meanings that tell the reader to think and react in a particular way to your ideas. In providing the reader with these important cues, transitions help readers understand the logic of how your ideas fit together. LOGICAL RELATIONSHIP TRANSITIONAL EXPRESSION Similarity also, in the same way, just as ... so too, likewise, similarly Exception/Contrast but, however, in spite of, on the one hand ... on the other hand, nevertheless, nonetheless, notwithstanding, in contrast, on the contrary, still, yet Sequence/Order first, second, third, ... next, then, finally Time after, afterward, at last, before, currently, during, earlier, immediately, later, meanwhile, now, recently, simultaneously, subsequently, then Example for example, for instance, namely, specifically, to illustrate Emphasis even, indeed, in fact, of course, truly Place/Position above, adjacent, below, beyond, here, in front, in back, nearby, there Cause and Effect accordingly, consequently, hence, so, therefore, thus Additional Support or Evidence additionally, again, also, and, as well, besides, equally important, further, furthermore, in addition, moreover, then Conclusion/Summary finally, in a word, in brief, in conclusion, in the end, in the final analysis, on the whole, thus, to conclude, to summarize, in sum, in summary Grammar and Spelling: You must make certain that your paper is free from grammar and spelling mistakes. Mechanical errors are usually the main reason for lack of clarity in essays, so be sure to thoroughly proof read your paper before handing it in. References: You must reference any material. You can duplicate the entry that you made in the database. ONE MORE TIME: Plagiarism and academic honesty: Plagiarism is a form of stealing; as with other offences against the law, ignorance is no excuse. The way to avoid plagiarism is to give credit where credit is due. If you are using someone else’s idea, acknowledge it, even if you have changed the wording or just summarized the main points. To avoid plagiarism, you must give credit whenever you use • • • • another person's idea, opinion, or theory; any facts, statistics, graphs, drawings--any pieces of information--that are not common knowledge; quotations of another person's actual spoken or written words; or paraphrase of another person's spoken or written words. You should refer to the materials in the week of March 1 – 5 on identifying and avoiding plagiarism. If you have any additional questions, consult with your course assistant. SOURCES The information included in the document “Writing a Position Paper” was adapted from the following sources: Johnson-Sheehan R., & Paine C. (2018). Writing Today. [VitalSource Bookshelf]. Retrieved from https://bookshelf.vitalsource.com/#/books/9780134771717/ Writing a position paper: https://www.sfu.ca/cmns/130d1/WritingaPositionPaper.htm UHWO Writing Center (1998) Writing a Position Paper. Retrieved August 26, 2002 from the World Wide Web: http://homepages.uhwo.hawaii.edu/~writing/position.htm Position paper examples from: charon.athabascau.ca/cnhsundergrad/438c7/resources/resource_links/Position_Papers.html Grading Rubric for Reflections This rubric outlines the criteria that will be applied in grading your reflections. It should guide what you include in your reflection. All criteria are weighted equally in assigning your grade. DESCRIBING EXPERIENCE UNDEVELOPED (0 pt) DEVELOPING (1 pt) Unclear and vague Clear but general SKILLED (2 pt) Unclear and vague Some response but limited to one domain (e.g., only emotional, intellectual) or to reflection only, without indication of conscious contemporaneous reflection. Reflection – Making connection between student’s personal assumptions, habits, or values and the opinions or behaviors upon which the student is reflecting. Clear and focused description of the feelings, thoughts, and questions raised by the student at the time of the experience and upon reflection. Provides a description of the readings upon which he or she is reflecting DESCRIBING RESPONSE Provides a description of their intellectual and emotional response to the experience GENERAL REFLECTION Evidence of questioning or evaluating their prior perceptions, actions, or beliefs USING INSIGHTS Student’s reflection leads to plans for future action Minimal reflection – No personal reflection or limited to description of general opinions and behaviors without reflection on underlying assumptions, habits, or values driving those opinions or behaviors. Students reflection is entirely backward looking, with no indication of how the student will use the insights and skills gained. Student has generalized statements regarding how the reflection will direct future actions or beliefs Clear and focused on the specific aspects that challenge the student Critical reflection – Critical evaluation (questioning, examining more closely) student’s personal assumptions, habits, or values and their connection to the opinions or behaviors upon which the student is reflecting in light of other perspectives. Student provides concrete plans for further action or reflection for a specific purpose such as developing skills, improving self-understanding, or refining belief systems CONNECTIONS TO Does not include any READING/RESEARCH reference to outside reading or research Uses coursework, to inform reflection reading, orindependent research toadvance reflection as appropriate. CONNECTIONS TO PEOPLE Engages instructors, mentors, colleagues, and others in reflection by referencing insights gained from course activities. WRITING QUALITY Quality of writing indicates careful attention to reflective practice by providing clear topic, using concrete and precise language, organizing thoughts for the reader, and proofreading essay for grammar, punctuation, and spelling Demonstrates no effort to engage others in reflecting on the experience or insights. Unfocused, unorganized, vague, and sloppy Reflection refers to past readings or research in a descriptive or citation fashion with little indication of motivation to use reading or research to inform reflection Connects reflection to past readings and research and indicates efforts to re-read or conduct additional research to learn more about aspects of the experience upon which reflection occurs. Describes specific insights or extensions of reflection gained from that reading and research. Describes some Demonstrates conversations or meaningful interviews regarding conversations with the experience or others to test ideas reflection but only in and gain insights on an incidental the experience and fashion, rather than reflection. as an effort to test ideas or gain insights Some focus and Topic(s) are clear organization. and specific, Language has some descriptions use precision. concrete and precise Essay was proofread language and insights are precise and clear, Organization is apparent and effective. Essay has been proofread for grammar, punctuation, and spelling errors.

Option 1

Low Cost Option
Download this past answer in few clicks

16.89 USD

PURCHASE SOLUTION

Already member?


Option 2

Custom new solution created by our subject matter experts

GET A QUOTE